Consciousness 1: The neural correlates of consciousness (neurological perspective) (v1.0)
This
is the highlight of an article from the economist that I thought was
interesting.
The greatest
question posed in science is what is consciousness? "I think, therefore I
am." Rene Descartes’ aphorism has become a cliche. As Descartes
observation suggests, a conscious being knows he/she is conscious. But he
cannot know that any other being is. Consciousness is subjective. Other
apparently conscious individuals might be zombies programmed to behave as if
they were conscious, without actually being so (though for other humans it is
farfetched to believe so). It gets even muddier with other species. Are
chimpanzees conscious? Dogs? Codfish? Bees? It is hard to know how to ask them
in a meaningful way.
Blindsight
is an interesting neurological disorder - it happens when blindness is caused
due to certain damage to visual cortex in the brain. Those who have blindsight
have no conscious awareness of being able to see. They are nevertheless able to
point to, and even grasp, objects in their visual field. This illustrates how
apparently conscious actions can occur without consciousness.
There
are many dimensions to a study of consciousness in humans (like evolutionary
perspective, neurological perspective, philosophical perspective, and
psychological perspective). Here I will focus on only neurological aspects. The
views here are not harmonized with views from other dimensions.
There
has been a search for the neural correlates of consciousness. A person could suffer the loss of the cerebellum or
large bilateral portions of the medial temporal lobes, including amygdala and
hippocampus complex, and would not become unconscious. This points to
specific areas related to consciousness. Cortical lesions for example can
result in such specific impairments of consciousness where one may no longer be
able to speak, perceive color, or identify parts of themselves as their
own.
One
potential neural correlates of particular interest are claustrum (one in each
hemisphere). In 2003, Crick (father of DNA) and Koch formed a hypothesis about
the central role of Claustrum in consciousness. The claustrum has extensive
connections to other parts of the brain. The pair are thin sheets of nerve
cells tucked below the cerebral cortex that have connections both to and from
almost every area of the cortex. They are the only structures that link the
various parts of the cortex in this way. A crucial property of
consciousness is that it integrates many sorts of experiences, both sensory and
internally generated. In 2005 a paper looked at this problem. They suggested
they act like orchestral conductors, coordinating the activities of the cortical
components and thus solving the integration problem. In 2014 Mohamad
Koubeissi, an American neurologist while studying a epilepsy patent, put
an electrode near a claustrum. When the switch was turned on, the patient lost
consciousness. When turned off, consciousness returned. He got the same results
when tried multiple times. A relatively recent paper suggests more specifically
how claustrum may be involved in consciousness in the temporal arena: Claustrum, consciousness, and time perception -
ScienceDirect
Another
clue is gamma waves. Gamma waves (electrical impulses at 40HZ that beat in synchrony
in different parts of the brain) is strongest during conscious concentration on
tasks, and always present when conscious, but largely disappear when asleep
unless the person is dreaming. Many neuroscientists suspect gamma wave
synchrony means they are acting like the clock in a computer processor,
coordinating the activities of different parts of the brain.
Yet
another potential neural correlate is temporoparietal junction (one in each
hemisphere). The brain consists of multiple
lobes including the frontal lobe, the parietal lobe, the temporal lobe, and the
occipital lobe. The place where the temporal and parietal lobes come together
is called the temporoparietal junction. Damage to this part of the
brain (or turning it off temporarily with transcranial magnetic stimulation - TMS)
creates strange effects that include out of body experiences in which a
person's conscious perception of himself appears (from his point of view) to
detach itself from his body. It also reduces one's ability to empathize with
the mental state of others. That suggests this part of the brain helps generate
"theory of mind" - the ability to recognize that other creatures too,
have minds. Since the only model available to a mind that wishes to understand another’s
is itself, a theory of mind necessarily requires self-awareness. Human babies
are able to do so from 18 months on.
Finding
the neural correlates of consciousness, or even understanding what it is for
and how it evolved may eventually get resolved but does not truly address the
question of what it actually is— what is it people are experiencing while they
are conscious. This question has come to be known as the “hard problem” of
consciousness (so dubbed in 1995 by David Chalmers, an Australian philosopher).
It is both hard to resolve and at the same time its resolution is the heart of
the matter. This really hard problem of consciousness is the problem of
experience. When we think and perceive, there is a whir of
information-processing, but there is also a subjective aspect. As Nagel (1974)
has put it, there is something "it is like" to be a conscious
organism. Here is Chalmers paper: Microsoft Word - facing.doc (consc.net)
Comments